Towards a Theory
of
Patriarchy
Sylvia Walby
From Polity Press (Eds.) (1994) The
Polity Reader in Gender Studies, Cambridge: Polity Press
The patriarchal mode of production necessarily exists
in articulation with another mode of production. The husband uses his labour power which
has been produced by the domestic labourer within this other. mode. Because he
has control over his labour power he has possession of the proceeds from
putting it into action. Within the
patriarchal mode of production, the husband does not use the proceeds of his
labour. power to compensate the domestic labourer
fully for the work she puts into producing it.
It is crucial to be able to explain why the woman does
not set up oil her own to produce lower power and why
she remains in the home to produce the labour power of her husband. I would argue that the reason for this
varies according to the mode of production with which the patriarchal mode is
in articulation. When the
patriarchal mode articulates with the capitalist mode, the primary mechanism
which ensures that women will serve their husbands is their exclusion from paid
work on the same terms as men.
Patriarchal relations within waged work arc crucial in preventing women
from entering that work as freely as men, and are reinforced by patriarchal
state policies. However, other sets
of patriarchal relations are also important. When the patriarchal mode of production
articulates with other modes, other levels of the social formation
become critical for the continuation of the patriarchal one. Under feudalism, for instance, fertility
and reproduction are of critical significance. This dynamic articulation with
capitalism will be further explored later.
I do not wish to suggest that the patriarchal mode of
production has any autonomous laws of development. On the contrary, I would suggest that
the other mode of production with which the patriarchal mode is in articulation
is particularly important in governing the nature of change. This does not
discredit the concept of patriarchal mode of production since the central
element in this is not its laws of motion, but rather that of the extraction of
surplus. It is the highly
distinctive method of extraction of surplus within patriarchy (which plays a
key role in the determination of other gender relations) which is the basis of
the claim that there is a patriarchal mode of production.
The patriarchal division of labour in the household
does not completely determine the form of patriarchal relations in a particular
society,; other sets of patriarchal relations also
have significance. A most important
set of patriarchal relations when the patriarchal mode of production is in
articulation with capitalism is that in paid work. Patriarchal relations in paid work are
necessary, if not sufficient, to the retention of women as unpaid labourers in
the household. The control of
women's access 'o paid work is maintained primarily by patriarchal relations in
the workplace and in the state, as well as by those in the household.
The form of this control has varied with time and
place to a significant extent. The
forms of control include non-admittance of women to forms of training, such as
apprenticeships and university degrees which are a condition of practising a
particular trade; the non-admittance of women to certain occupations; the
restriction of the percentage of women in certain occupations (e.g. the quota
on women which has historically been imposed by medical schools);
discrimination in hiring practices which reduces or eliminates the number of
women in a particular occupation; the ejection of women from an occupation, or
the reduction in their rights to remain in it on marriage; the sacking of
women, and in particular married women, before men in situations of redundancy;
the sacking of part-timers, who are almost exclusively married women, before
full-timers in situations of redundancy; practices such as 'last-in, first
out', the indirect consequence of which is that women go before men; the
ejection of women from certain occupations by legislative action; the
restriction on the amount of certain kinds of paid work that women can do, with
implications for their entry to those occupations at all, such as the reduction
in women's hours in the Factory Acts of the nineteenth century. These exclusionary practices fall into
two types: restriction of entry to particular occupations; and ways of ejecting
women, rather than men, from certain occupations. They exist in varying forms of
directness, from rigid rules which are consistently enforced, such as the ban
on women taking degrees at universities in the UK before the late nineteenth
century, to more indirect forms which may not always produce the same effect,
such as the 'last-in, first-out' practice in redundancy situations.
The agents carrying out these exclusionary practices
include male dominated trade unions; other male-dominated organisations;
prejudiced employers; and the state.
The immediate social and historical context in which these practices
have existed is also immensely varied,
Most existing analyses of patriarchy have taken
patriarchal relations in the workplace insufficiently into account. Yet an adequate analysis of patriarchy
must incorporate this as a highly significant element. These forms of exclusionary practice may
be seen as a form of social closure.
They are both a product of, and themselves create, highly significant
divisions among paid workers. They
are to a considerable extent a result of patriarchal divisions elsewhere in
society, especially in the household, but cannot be reduced to these. There is an extent to which the
struggles around these practices have their own autonomy. However, the resources which are brought
to these struggles are related to the resources available to the competing
groups in different areas of social life.
Patriarchal relations in the workplace and the state
as well as the family are central to the determination of the position of women
in paid work. Capital and
patriarchy have rival interests in women's labour.,
and the position that women hold in paid work cannot be understood without an
analysis of the tension between the two.
There are theoretical reasons for the importance of paid work for
contemporary gender relations: paid work is a crucial site in capitalist relations
and this i,., transmitted to the relations between
patriarchal structures when the system of patriarchy is in articulation with
capitalism.
The state is a site of patriarchal relations which is
necessary to patriarchy as a whole.
The state represents patriarchal as well as capitalist interests and
furthers them in its actions. This
conception of the state as patriarchal as well as capitalist runs counter to
most other analyses of it; most accounts do not consider gender relations at
all, focusing instead on class relations within capitalism and the relations
between these and the state. Such
accounts of the state are inadequate in that they fail to take into account
either the impact of gender inequality and women's political struggles on the
state, or the significance of state actions on gender relations. The omissions are serious both because
these are significant dimensions of state action, and because they lead to a
flawed analysis of the issues that these writers purport to address. For instance, an analysis of the
development of the welfare state which does not take into account the role of
women's political struggles as women would be seriously in error as to the
political forces which were operating in that situation. Yet this has been a common practice in
much writing on the development of the welfare state.
However, there have been important, if rare, attempts
to analyse the relationship between the state and the position of women
seriously. Mclntosh[1] suggests that the state upholds the oppression of
women by supporting a form of household in which women provide unpaid domestic
services for a male.' She argues that the state should be viewed as capitalist,
since it is acting to maintain the capitalist mode of production. Capitalism benefits from a particular
form of family which ensures the cheap reproduction of labour power and the
availability of women as a reserve army of labour. She suggests, however, that the family
is not the ideal form for the reproduction of labour power for two reasons. First, the ratio of earner to dependent
is widely variable in actual families and thus some families cannot survive on
earned income. The state steps in
to shore up the family structure in those instances when it would otherwise
fail. Second, families by
themselves do not necessarily produce the right number of children to meet
capitalist requirements for population size, so sometimes explicit population
policies are introduced to ensure the maintenance of its members. Thus, for Mclntosh, the state's support
for the oppression of women is indirect, not direct, since it is through the
maintenance of this family form that the state acts to the detriment of women.
While Mclntosh does point to various contradictions in
capitalism and in state policy her argument nonetheless hinges on the notion
that the family is maintained because it is functional for capitalism. This position is problematic in that it
does not take sufficient account of the benefits that men derive from the
contemporary family structure, and of the divergence between patriarchal and
capitalist interests, such as whether women should stay at home or take paid
work. Further, the analysis pays
insufficient attention to the struggles that take place on the political level
which need to be accorded greater autonomy in the analysis.
I would argue that, when patriarchy is in articulation
with capitalism, the state should be seen as both patriarchal and
capitalist. Such a dualist
conception of the state is only a problem if the state is incorrectly
considered to act in a monolithic manner.
Much of the recent literature on the capitalist state sees state actions
as the result of the political struggle of competing classes and class
fractions, so one more set of competing interests is not an insuperable
conceptual problem. The state
should be considered equally an arena for political struggle and an actor
intervening in particular situations.
Its actions should be seen as the result of the struggles between
different interests. It should not
be seen as the instrument of a dominant class or class fraction.
In a theory like this, it is possible to conceive of
the state as both patriarchal and capitalist. Its specific actions in any instance are
the outcome of the struggle on the political level of the competing interests
involved in both patriarchal and capitalist relations. The state should not be reduced to, or
derived from, the economic level, but rather the political level should be seen
to have considerable autonomy. Any
theory of a patriarchal and capitalist state must analyse the struggles of
patriarchal and capitalist interests as they are represented on the political
level, while also tracing the links to other levels, especially the economic,
The intervention of the state has been, at certain
times, of crucial significance in the shaping of patriarchal relations in
society. Yet at the same time it is
not the basis of patriarchal power.
Rather its actions should be seen as the outcome of the representation
of patriarchal interests which are mediated in the political process. While the actions of the state are
linked to the economic level of patriarchy, they have a level of autonomy in
which the actual outcome of conflicting interests is mediated by conflicts and
negotiation at the political level.
Women, who are subordinated within the productive
process, have little access to forms of political representation. This is partly because of their lack of
power in the sphere of production, and partly because the particular forms of
the state and its mode of functioning act to suppress the effective
representation of women's interests.
In terms of the recent state in a society in which patriarchy
articulates with capitalism, these problems of representation have been
exacerbated by the late granting of the franchise to women and the formation of
the major political parties along lines of division representing the interests
of the classes of the capitalist rather than the patriarchal system. Thus there i,,-,
a limited historic tradition of women's participation in parliamentary politics
compounded by the absence of political parties organised around issues of
gender relations.
The state acts to support patriarchal relations in a
variety of ways. These include the
limiting of women's access to paid work (e.g. the Dilution Acts); the
criminalization of forms of fertility control (e.g. at certain times and places
abortion, contraception); support for the institution of marriage through, for
example, the cohabitation rule, discriminatory income maintenance and by
regulating marriage and divorce: actions against some sexual relations through,
for instance, criminalising, male homosexual relations in some periods and
denying custody of children to lesbian mothers; actions against radical dissent,
for instance, in the coercive response to the suffrage movement.
One example of the patriarchal actions of the state is
that which enabled male workers in the First World War to ensure their re-entry
into the relatively highly paid and skilled engineering jobs that they ceded to
women for the duration of the hostilities.
The economic pressures in this situation would have led the employers to
continue to employ the cheaper women workers, if they had been able. However, male workers such as the engineers
had sufficient power in conjunction with the government to prevent this from
occurring. These men had power in
the labour process in that only they could effectively train new workers, and
this enabled them to have the power to refuse to train new female
employees. The men also had
political power in that their interests were represented in the state to a
greater extent than that of women, and they were organised in a powerful and
effective body in the Amalgamated Society of Engineers. Women, by contrast, had little economic
or political power, not even having the right to vote, at this time.
Here we see both the limits and the significance of
patriarchal state power. There were
limits in that it required other bases of patriarchal power to mobilise the
state's resources on behalf of patriarchal interests; and significance in that
it prevented the erosion of that form of patriarchal power which was based in
the exclusion of women from the skilled engineering trades.
Another example of the patriarchal nature of the state
is its response (or rather lack of response) to male violence against women in
contemporary Britain. Here women's
lack of access to state power ensures that men who rape, batter and otherwise
molest women will rarely be punished by the criminal justice system. Women's interests are not sufficiently
represented in the state to force any consistency between the rhetoric - that
the state attempts to protect everyone against illegal violence - and the
reality of widespread male violence against women.
Minor modifications to the state's practices on this
issue of men's violence to women have taken place in times of feminist
agitation. For instance, in 1976
the Sexual Offences Amendment Act was passed with the express purpose of giving
a raped woman anonymity and of preventing her sexual
history being discussed in court. A
further example is the introduction, at the end of the nineteenth century, of
violence as a sufficient reason for judicial separation. Both these reforms occurred in periods
of feminist activity, which led to an increase in the representation of women's
interests at the level of the state on the issue of male violence. This is an example of the relative
autonomy of the state from the economy and of the significance of events at the
political level affecting state actions.
But again, there are limits to the significance of the state, in that no
serious possibility of effective state action against violent men is possible while
the material basis of patriarchy exists.
This lack of prosecution of men who are violent
towards women raises important questions as to the traditional definition of
the state as a body which has the monopoly of legitimate violence in a given
territory. I would argue that the
state de facto accepts male violence
against women as legitimate, despite its being carried out by agents who are
not usually considered as part of the state apparatus. According to the traditional definition,
these violent men must then be seen as agents of the state in carrying out this
violence. I would suggest that an
alternative approach might be to modify the definition of the state so that it
is no longer defined as having the monopoly on legitimate violence. The first position is problematic in
that it involves a movement away from the notion of the state as a centralised
cohesive body. I would suggest that
this is central to the notion of the state. Instead the notion of having the
monopoly on legitimate violence should be modified in recognition of men's unpunished violence against women.
Reference
[1] M. Mclntosh, 'The state and the oppression of women',
in Feminism and Materialism, ed. Annette Kuhn and Ann Marie Wolpe (Routledge and Kegan Paul, London,
1978).